Let’s say I present you with a portfolio of five stocks, and ask you to predict each stock’s price one year from now. You know the current prices, and you know stocks are pretty volatile, but absent any special reason to think five companies are more likely to have good years than bad ones, you write down the current price as your best prediction for all five slots.
Then I write a paper accusing you of suffering from an “end of financial history illusion.” After all, on average you predicted that the stock values won’t change at all over six months — but in reality, stock prices change a lot! If I compute how much each of the five stock prices changed over the last six months, and average those numbers, I get something pretty big. And yet you, you crazy thing, seem to believe that the stock prices, having arrived at their current values, are to be fixed in place forever more.
Pretty bad argument, right?
And yet the same computation, applied to five personality traits instead of five stocks, got published in Science. Quoidbach, Gilbert, and Wilson write:
In study 1, we sought to determine whether people underestimate the extent to which their personalities will change in the future. We recruited a sample of 7519 adults ranging in age from 18 to 68 years [mean (M) = 40 years, standard deviation (SD) = 11.3 years, 80% women] through the Web site of a popular television show and asked them to complete the Ten Item Personality Inventory (1), which is a standard measure of the five trait dimensions that underlie human personality (i.e., conscientiousness, agreeableness, emotional stability, openness to experience, and extraversion). Participants were then randomly assigned either to the reporter condition (and were asked to complete the measure as they would have completed it 10 years earlier) or the predictor condition (and were asked to complete the measure as they thought they would complete it 10 years hence). We then computed the absolute value of the difference between participants’ ratings of their current personality and their reported or predicted personality and averaged these across the five traits to create a measure of reported or predicted change in personality.
This study is getting a lot of press: it was written up in the New York Times (why, oh why, is it always John Tierney?), USA Today, and Time, and even made it to Mathbabe.
Unfortunately, it’s wrong.
The difference in predictions is not the predicted difference
The error here is just the same as in the story of the stocks. The two quantities
- The difference between the predicted future value and the current value
- The predicted difference between the future value and the current value
sound like the same thing. But they’re not the same thing. Life’s noncommutative that way sometimes. Quoidbach et al are measuring the former quantity and referring to it as if it’s the latter.
You can see the difference even in a very simple model. Let’s say the ways a stock works is that, over six months, there’s a 30% chance it goes up a dollar, a 25% chance it goes down a dollar, and a 45% chance it stays the same. And let’s say you know this. Then your estimated expected value of the stock price six months from now is “price now + 5 cents,” and the first number — the size of difference between your predicted value and the current value is 5 cents.
But what’s the second number? In your model, the difference between the future price and the current price has a 55% chance of being a dollar and a 45% chance of being zero. So your prediction for the size of the difference is 55 cents — 11 times as much!
If you measure the first quantity and say you’ve measured the second, you’re gonna have a bad time.
In the “predictor” condition of the paper, a rational respondent quizzed about a bunch of stocks will get a score of about 5 cents. What about the “reporter” condition? Then the respondent’s score will be the average value of the difference between the price six months ago and the price now; this difference will be a dollar 55% of the time and zero 45% of the time, so the scores in the reporter condition will average 55 cents.
To sum up: completely rational respondents with full information ought to display the behavior observed by Quoidbach et al — precisely the behavior the authors adduce as evidence that their subjects are in the grips of a cognitive bias!
To get mathy with it for a minute — if Y is the value of a variable at some future time, and X is the value now, the two quantities are
Those numbers would be the same if absolute value were a linear function. But absolute value isn’t a linear function. Unless, that is, you know a priori that Y -X was positive. In other words, if people knew for certain that over a decade they’d get less extraverted, but didn’t know to what extent, you might expect to see the same scores appearing in the predictor and reporter conditions. But this is not, in fact, something people know about themselves.
I always think I’m right but I don’t think I’m always right
The study I’ve mentioned isn’t the only one in the paper. Here’s another:
[In study 3]…we recruited a new sample of 7130 adults ranging from 18 to 68 years old (M = 40.2 years, SD = 11.1 years, 80% women) through the same Web site and asked them to report their favorite type of music, their favorite type of vacation, their favorite type of food, their favorite hobby, and the name of their best friend. Participants were then randomly assigned either to the reporter condition (and were asked to report whether each of their current preferences was the same as or different than it was 10 years ago) or the predictor condition (and were asked to predict whether each of their current preferences would be the same or different 10 years from now). We then counted the number of items on which participants responded “different” and used this as a measure of reported or predicted changes in preference.
Let’s say I tend to change my favorite music (respectively vacation, food, hobby, and friend) about once every 25 years, so that there’s about a 40% chance that in a given ten-year period I’ll make a change. And let’s say I know this about myself, and I’m free from cognitive biases. If you ask me to predict whether I’ll have the same or different favorite food in ten years, I’ll say “same” — after all, there’s a 60-40 chance that’s correct! Ditto for the other four categories.
Once again, Quoidbach et al refer to the number of times I answer “different” as “a measure of predicted changes in preference.” But it isn’t — or rather, it has nothing to say about the predicted number of changes. If you ask me “How many of the five categories do you think I’ll change in the next ten years?” I’ll say “two.” While if you ask me, for each of the five categories in turn, “Do you think you’ll change this in the next ten years?” I’ll say no, five times straight. This is not a contradiction and it is not a failure of rationality and it is not a cognitive bias. It is math, done correctly.
(Relevant philosophical maxim about groundedness of belief: “I always think I’m right, but I don’t think I’m always right.” We correctly recognize that some subset of things we currently believe are wrong, but each particular belief we take as correct. Update: NDE in comments reminds me that WVO Quine is the source of the maxim.)
What kind of behavior would the authors consider rational in this case? Presumably, one in which the proportion of “different” answers is the same in the prospective and retrospective conditions. In other words, I’d score as bias-free if I answered
“My best friend and my favorite music will change, but my favorite food, vacation, and hobby will stay the same.”
This answer has a substantially smaller chance of being correct than my original one. (108/3125 against 243/3125, if you’re keeping score at home.) The author’s suggestion that it represents a less biased response is wrong.
Now you may ask: why didn’t Quoidbach et al just directly ask people “to what extent do you expect your personality to change over the next ten years?” and compare that with retrospective report? To their credit, they did just that — and there they did indeed find that people predicted smaller changes than they reported:
Third, is it possible that predictors in study 1 knew that they would change over the next 10 years, but because they did not know exactly how they would change, they did not feel confident predicting specific changes? To investigate this possibility, we replicated study 1 with an independent sample of 1163 adults (M = 38.4 years, SD = 12.1 years, 78% women) recruited through the same Web site. Instead of being asked to report or predict their specific personality traits, these participants were simply asked to report how much they felt they had “changed as a person over the last 10 years” and how much they thought they would “change as a person over the next 10 years.” Because some participants contributed data to both conditions, we performed a multilevel version of the analysis described in study 1. The analysis revealed the expected effect of condition (β = –0.74, P = 0.007), indicating that predictors aged a years predicted that they would change less over the next decade than reporters aged a + 10 years reported having changed over the same decade. This finding suggests that a lack of specific knowledge about how one might change in the future was not the cause of the effects seen in study 1.
This study, unlike the others, addresses the question the paper proposes to consider. To me, it seems questionable that numerical answers to “how much will you change as a person in the next 10 years?” are directly comparable with numerical answers to “how much did you change as a person over the last 10 years?” but this is a question about empirical social science, not mathematics. Even if I were a social scientist, I couldn’t really judge this part of the study, because the paragraph I just quoted is all we see of it — how the questions were worded, how they were scored, what the rest of the coefficients in the regression were, etc, are not available, either in the main body of the paper or the supplementary material.
[Update: Commenter deinst makes the really important point that Quoidbach et al have made their data publicly available at the ICPSR repository, and that things like the exact wording of the questions, the scoring mechanism, are available there.]
Do we actually underestimate the extent to which we’ll change our personalities and preferences over time? It certainly seems plausible: indeed, other researchers have observed similar effects, and the “changed as a person” study in the present paper is suggestive in this respect.
But much of the paper doesn’t actually address that question. Let me be clear: I don’t think the authors are trying to put one over. This is a mistake — a somewhat subtle mistake, but a bad mistake, and one which kills a big chunk of the paper. Science should not have accepted the article in its current form, and the authors should withdraw it, revise it, and resubmit it.
Yes, I know this isn’t actually going to happen.
Like this:
Like Loading...